Voluntary euthanasia under control? 
The latest empirical evidence on euthanasia in the Netherlands

 

Henk Jochemsen and John Keown

Lindeboom Institute for Medical Ethics, the Netherlands and University of Cambridge, respectively

 

Abstract

Nineteen ninety-six saw the publication of a major Dutch survey into euthanasia in the Netherlands. This paper outlines the main statistical findings of this survey and considers whether it shows that voluntary euthanasia is under effective control in the Netherlands.  The paper concludes that although there has been some improvement in compliance with procedural requirements, the practice of voluntary euthanasia remains beyond effective control.

(Journal of Medical Ethics 1999;25(1):16-21. Reproduced with permission)

 

Keywords: Euthanasia; the Netherlands; regulation; slippery slope

 

Introduction

   Worldwide, the euthanasia debate continues to intensify.  In 1997, the Australian parliament voted to repeal euthanasia legislation in the Northern Territory and the US Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of legislation prohibiting "physician-assisted suicide"(1). In deciding whether euthanasia or assisted suicide should be permitted in principle, and whether they can be controlled in practice, the experience of the Netherlands, where they have been officially tolerated and widely practised for well over a decade, is clearly of pro­found importance.

   Nineteen ninety-one saw the publication of the results of an important survey, by Professor PJ van der Maas, into end-of-life decision making by Dutch doctors in the year 1990 (2). Despite claims to the contrary by supporters of Dutch euthanasia, this survey helped to cast serious doubt on Dutch claims that their guidelines were sufficiently strict effectively to control the practice of voluntary euthanasia (the intentional termination of pa­tients' lives at their request) and to prevent non-voluntary euthanasia (the intentional termi­nation of the lives of patients incapable of making a request).

   The survey disclosed the widespread practice of non-voluntary euthanasia; the use of euthanasia even when doctors thought that palliative care was a viable alternative, and the common practice by doctors of illegally certifying euthanasia deaths as deaths by "natural causes" instead of reporting them, as required by the guidelines, to the authorities (3).

   In 1996, Van der Maas and Van der Wal published the results of an extensive survey into end-of-life decisions by Dutch doctors in the year 1995 (4). Do the results of this survey show any improvement in the degree of control over eutha­nasia?

 

I The survey

   The survey sought particularly to ascertain the incidence of intentional life-shortening by doc­tors; the extent to which they complied with their duty to report such cases (in accordance with a procedure dating from late 1990 which was given statutory force in june 1994), and the quality of their reporting.  The main purpose of the report­ing procedure is to provide for possible scrutiny of the intentional termination of life by doctors and to promote careful decision making in such cases (5). The most important quantitative data generated by the survey are reproduces in table 1.

   Before the figures are analysed, it is important to note that the only objectively verifiable figures are those concerning the total number of deaths and the total number of cases reported.  All the other figures are based en the responsos of the physicians concerning cases in which they said they had recently been involved.

   It is no less important to stress that this paper does not question the methodology used by the rescarchers to obtain their data, namely, inter­views with 405 physicians and postal questionnaires mailed to physicians who had attended 6.060 deaths identified from death certificases.  We use the researchers' own data and standardly cite their "best estimate" (though in some cases num­bers have been arrived at en the basis of percent­ages and numbers used in the survey and, in such cases, we have rounded off the number arrived at).

 

 In other words, our paper does not take issue with the researchers' methodology but with their interpretation of the statistics it generated.

A final preliminary point is that the Dutch adopt a particularly narrow definition of "eutha­nasia" as the intentional shortening of a patient's life at the patient's explicit request.  In other words, "euthanasia" in the Netherlands means "active, voluntary euthanasia" and does not include intentional life-shortening by omission ("passive euthanasia") or euthanasia without the patient's request (whether non-voluntary if the patient is incompetent or involuntary if the patient is competent.) For ease of exposition, the Dutch definition is followed here unless the contrary is apparent.

 

1. EUTHANASIA AND ASSISTED SUICIDE

Between 1990 and 1995 the number of requests for euthanasia increased, as did the number of requests granted.' Cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide rose from 2,700 cases in 1990 to 3,600 in 1995, or from 2. 1 % to 2.7% of all deaths.

According to the attending physicians, there were treatment alternativas in 17% of these cases but in almost all the patients did not want them (7).  However, in 1994, the Dutch Supreme Court held that doctors should not hasten death whenever the alternativa of palliative treatment was available, at least in cases of mental suffering (8) and the ministers of justice and health (9) and the Royal Dutch Medical Association (KNMG)(10) have decided that the same restriction should apply in cases of somatic suffering.  The above cases appear, therefore, to have breached this guideline.

Life was shortened by one to four weeks in 31% of euthanasia cases and 45% of assisted suicides and by more than a month in 7% of cases of euthanasia and in 30% of assisted suicides (11).

                        Physicians stated that the main reason why patients requested euthanasia was "intolerable suffering without prospect of improvement" (74%)(12), which has become the standard termi­nology to describe the seriousness of the condition required by the law.  But the next most common reasons were "to prevent loss of dignity" (56%) and "to prevent further suffering" (47%).  It must surely be doubted whether either of these reasons, by itself, satisfies the requirement of unbearable suffering.

                        Interestingly, one of the most important reasons for rejecting a request for euthanasia (cited by 35% of physicians) was the physician's opinion that the patient's suffering was not intolerable (13). This suggests that, despite the emphasis placed by the advocates of euthanasia on patient autonomy, the application of euthanasia is more a function of the physicans judgment about the quality of the patient's life than of respect for the patient's autonomy.  This suggestion is fortified by the evidence about the extent to which Dutch doctors continue to terminate the lives of patients without an explicit request.

 

2. LIFE-TERMINATING ACTIONS WITHOUT EXPLICIT REQUEST

   The survey confirms that the intentional shorten­ing of patients' lives without explicit request remains far from uncommon.  Nine hundred patients had their lives ended without explicit request in 1995, representing 0.7% of all deaths, only a slight decrease en the 0.8% so terminated in 1990 (14). In other words, of the 4,500 (3,200 + 400 + 900) cases in which doctors admitted they actively and intentionally terminated life, one in five involved no explicit request.

   The main reason for not discussing the issue with the patient was stated to be the patient's incompetence (due, for example, to dementia).  But not all patients whose lives were terminated without an explicit request were incompetente. In 15% of cases where no discussion took place but could have, the doctor did not discuss the termination of life because the doctor thought that the termination of the patient's life was clearly in the patient's best interests (15).

   Furthermore, in a third of the 900 cases, there had been a discussion with the patient about the possible termination of life, and some 50% of these patients were fully competent, yet their lives were terminated without an explicit request (16).

   Moreover, in 17% of the 900 cases, treatment alternativas were thought to be available by the attending physician (17).

   The physicians thought that life was shortened by one to four weeks in 3% of cases but by more than a month in 6%.(18) Finally, physicians had not discussed their action with a colleague in 40% of cases, with a close relative in 30% of cases, and with anyone at all in 5%.(19)

 

3. INTENSIFICATION OF PAIN AND SYMPTOM TREATMENT

   In 20,000 cases (according to the physician inter­views) or 25,800 cases (according to the death certificase survey), palliative drugs were adminis­tered in doses which almost certainly shortened life.  In some 2,000 of these cases the doctor explicitly intended, and in a further 2,850 cases, partly intended, to shorten life.(20) The researchers estimate that the grey area between intending to alleviate pain and symptoms and intending to shorten life is about 2% of all deaths, the same as in 1990.(21)

   Where doctors administered palliative drugs partly in order to shorten life, they had discussed Ħt with the patient in just over half of the cases (52%) and in only 36% of the cases was there an explicit request for life-shortening doses by the patient.  The physicians stated that 86 patients (3%) with whom they had not discussed this treatment were fully competent (22). Moreover, in only 36% of the cases had the doctors consulted a colleague.  Life was shortened by an estimated one to four weeks in 7% of cases but by more than a month in 1 %.(23)

 

4. WITHHOLDING/WITHDRAWING TREATMENT

In some 27,300 cases a treatment was withheld or withdrawn (in 5,200 cases at the patient's explicit request) taking into account a probable shorten­ing of life.

   However, in 18,000 of these cases (14,200 of which involved no explicit request by the patient) it was the physician's explicit intention to shorten life (though the survey does not state in how many cases the treatment was disproportionate, in which case doctors could, had they wished, have properly withdrawn it for that reason and without intending to shorten life).(24)

   In the majority of cases in which no discussion with the patient had taken place, the physicians stated that the patient was either incompetent or only partly competent. However, in 1 % of these cases (140 patients) the physician considered the patient fully competent.(25)

   In cases where treatment was withheld or with­drawn with the explicit intent to shorten life, the physician estimated that life was shortened by one to seven days in 34% of cases, by one to four weeks in 18% and by more than a month in 9%.(26)

 

5. NEONATES

   The survey reports that over 1,000 newborns die in the Netherlands before their first birthday and estimates that the lives of about 15 are actively and intentionally terminated by doctors.(27) The figure of 15 seems however, a significant underestimate.

   The survey shows that in ten cases (1 %) doctors administered a drug with the explicit intention of shortening life.  But it also reveals a further 80 cases in which, also with the explicit intention of shortening life, doctors administered a drug and withdrew or withheld a life-prolonging treatment.(28) In total, therefore, it appears to have been the explicit intention of doctors to shorten the lives of 90 neonates, not 15.(29)

   Moreover, in no fewer than 41% of the 1,000 cases, treatment was withdrawn or withheld with the explicit intention of shortening life.  In a significant proportion of these cases, life was terminated because the babies' lives were not thought bearable.  Forty-flve per cent of these babies were expected to live more than four weeks, and some of them more than half a year.(30)

   In around a fifth of cases in which doctors intentionally withheld or withdrew treatment with the explicit purpose of shortening life because the baby's life was thought unbearable, there had been no discussion with the parents.(31) Doctors said that in most cases this was because the situation was so clear that discussion was unnecessary or because there was no time, though these reasons are not elaborated.

   Finally, doctors reported hardly any cases ofthe intentional shortening of neonatal life to the authorities.

 

 

 6. ASSISTED SUICIDE OF PSYCHIATRIC PATIENTS

Based on the replies of psychiatrists in respect of the year 1995, the survey estimates that although some 320 psychiatric patients explicitly request assistance in suicide annually, only two to five are assisted to commit suicide by psychiatrists.  Among psychiatrists who would never grant a request for assisted suicide on the basis of mental suffering (almost 1/3 of the respondents) "profes­sional opinion" was cited by 88% as the most important reason.  Only 2% of psychiatrists had ever assisted suicide.(32)

                This relatively restrictive approach of psychia­trists may owe not a little to the controversy gen­erated by the case of Dr Chabot, a psychiatrist criticised by a medical disciplinary court for assisting in the suicide of a 50-year-old woman who suffered grief after the loss of her two sons.(33)

                Disclosing statistics which support a restrictive approach, the survey also indicates that of those patients not assisted in suicide, 16% committed suicide without assistance by a physician and that, of those patients still living, 35% no longer wished for death and that the death wish in a further 10 % had diminished.

 

7. CONSULTATION

   The guidelines for permissible euthanasia and assisted suicide require the doctor, before agree­ing to either, to engage in a formal consultation (consultatie), and not merely an informal discus­sion (overleg), with a colleague.

   In cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide 92% of doctors had, according to the survey, discussed the case with a colleague.(34) In 13% of these cases, however, the discussion did not amount to a formal consultation.  Consultation took place, therefore, in 79% of cases.  However, other figures in the survey suggest that consultation occurred in a significantly smaller percentage of cases.  For the survey indicates that consultation occurred in 99% of reported cases but in only 18% of unreported cases (35) and that almost 60% of all cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide were not reported,(36) from which it seems that consultation occurred in only around half of all cases.(37)

   In the cases of life-termination without explicit request, a discussion occurred in 43% of cases but in 40% this did not amount to consultation.  Con­sequently, there was no consultation in 97% of such cases.

   Moreover, even when consultation did take place, it was usually with a physician living locally and the most important reasons given for consult­ing such a physician were his views on life-ending decisions and his living nearby: expertise in pallia­tive care was hardly mentioned.  Further, in the overwhelming majority of cases, the first doctor had made his mind up before consulting and the doctor consulted disagreed in only 7% of cases.(38) In short, the requirement of consultation, even when it is satisfied, hardly operates as a rigorous check on decision making.

 

8. REPORTING

In 1995 41% of cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide were reported to the local medical examiner, as required by the reporting procedure. While this is an improvement on the figure of 18% reported in 1990, it means that a clear majority of cases, almost 60%, still go unreported.  Moreover, the survey confirms that the legal requirements are breached more frequently in unreported cases, in which there is less often a written request by the patient, a written record by the doctor, or consul­tation by the doctor.(39)

The most important reasons given by doctors for failing to report in 1995 were (as in 1990), the wish to avoid the inconvenience (for the doctor and/or the relatives) of an investigation by the authorities, and to avoid the risk of prosecution (though, as the consistently tiny number of prosecutions indicates, this risk is negligible).  Thirty per cent of doctors stated that they did not report because they had failed to observe the requirements for permissible euthanasia and 12% because they considered euthanasia was a private matter between doctor and patient.(40)

 

II Discussion

The second survey confirms at least three disturbing findings of the first survey

 

1. INCIDENCE OF INTENTIONAL LIFE-SHORTENING WITH AND WITHOUT EXPLICIT REQUEST

Like the first survey, the second indicates a sizeable incidence of intentional life-shortening by Dutch doctors.  Even adopting the unusually nar­row Dutch definition of euthanasia as active, vol­untary euthanasia there were no fewer than 3,200 cases in 1995 (2.4% of all deaths), an increase of almost a thousand on the 1990 total of 2,300 (1.8% of all deaths).

But if all cases in which doctors explicitly intended to shorten life (whether by act or omission, and whether with or without the patient's request) are included, the total rises steeply.  Adding the cases of assisted suicide (400); life-termination without explicit request (900) and the intensification of pain and symptom treatment with the explicit intent to shorten life (2,000), the total more than doubles from 3,200 to 6,500.

And if to this number are added the cases of withholding or withdrawing treatment with the explicit intent to shorten life (18,000)(41); cases in which neonates were intentionally terminated (90 cases) and psychiatric patients assisted in suicide (two to five cases), the total rises to over 24,500 cases.

 

2. EUTHANASIA AS AN ALTERNATIVE TO PALLIATIVE CARE

The survey's comment that "the quality of medi­cal treatment near the end of life has improved"(42) might not unreasonably be thought to display a certain complacency, particularly in a country which has some way to go in the provision of adequate palliative care.  The high incidence of intentional life-shortening disclosed by the survey and the relative weakness of the reasons for eutha­nasia given in many cases by the doctors tend to suggest that euthanasia is not confined to cases of "last resort" and is at least sometimes used as an alternativa to palliative care.  The case of Dr Chabot, in which the defendant doctor assisted a grieving woman, whom he did not consider to be physically or mentally ill, to kill herself, and in which the Supreme Court held that such suffering could indeed justify assisted suicide, ĦIlustrases the elasticity of the requirement of "unbearable suffering".

The survey confirms that, even when doctors believe that treatment alternativas are available, they not infrequently resort to euthanasia.  The opinion of the Supreme Court, the ministers of justice and health, and the KNMG, that euthana­sia is impermissible when treatment alternativas are available, even if the patient refuses them, has clearly not prevented its administration in such circumstances.  In a move that would make the prospect of prosecution even more remote, the then minister of justice appeared to reverse her earlier position and instructed the attorneys general that the refusal by the patient of available treatment alternativas does not tender euthanasia unlawful.(43)

 

3. WIDESPREAD BREACH OF THE REQUIREMENT TO REPORT

Although 41% of cases (1,466) were reported in 1995 as opposed to 18% (486) in 1990, it remains true that in both years, as in every year in between, a clear majority of cases has gone unreported.  There was, in short, no official control whatever over the majority of cases of euthanasia, assisted suicide or the termination of life without explicit request.

Nor should the alleged increase in reporting be accepted uncritically.  First, the second survey records an increase in cases of euthanasia between 1990 and 1995 (900 cases) almost as large as the increase in cases reported (980 cases).  Secondly, if the total of 6,500 cases of active, intentional life-shortening is used, then the proportion of unreported cases rises from 59% to 77%.  On the total of 24,500 cases, the proportion unreported reaches 94%.

   It will be recalled that the purpose of the reporting procedure is to allow for scrutiny of the intentional termination of life by doctors and to promote observance of the legal and professional requirements for euthanasia.  The undisputed fact that a clear majority of cases (59% according to the survey, at least 77% on our calculations) still goes unreported, serves only to reinforce doubts about the ability of the procedure to fulfil its pur­pose and to undermine Dutch claims of effective regulation, scrutiny and control.  Further, even those cases which are reported are reported by the doctor, and one may wonder whether the doctor's report is any more likely to disclose evidence of wrongdoing than is a tax return to disclose evidence of undeclared earnings.

 

Conclusions

With the publication of the first Van der Maas survey in 1991 it became clear that the so-called "strict safeguards" laid down in 1984 by the courts and the Royal Dutch Medical Association had largely failed.  The survey cast doubt on cen­tral assurances which had been given by the advo­cates of voluntary euthanasia: that euthanasia would be performed only at the patient's explicit request and that doctors terminating life without request would be prosecuted for murder; that euthanasia would be used only in cases of "last resort" and not as an alternativa to palliative care; and that cases would be openly reported and duly scrutinised.  The Dutch reaction to the survey's findings was also revealing: the cases of non­voluntary euthananasia Ħt disclosed, far from being criticised, were largely condoned.  In short, the survey indicated that, in less than a decade, the Dutch had slid down the slippery slope.

   It is therefore surprising that an American commentator should observe that the similarity between the findings in respect of 1990 and 1995 shows that the Dutch are apparently not descend­ing a slippery slope.(44) This observation quite over­looks the fact that the first survey showed that the descent had already occurred by 1990: the second survey, far from showing that there has been no descent from 1984 to 1995 shows merely that there has been no significant ascent from 1990 to 1995.

   The second survey is little more reassuring than the first.  Dutch proponents of voluntary euthana­sia claimed that tolerating voluntary euthanasia, subject to "safeguards", would allow it to be "brought into the open" and effectively controlled.  As the valuable surveys by Van der Maas and Van der Wal disclose, and as severas expert commentators have now concluded,(45) the reality is that a clear majority of cases of eutanasia both with and without request, go unreported and unchecked.(46) In the face of the undisputed fact that in a clear majority of cases there is not even an opportunity for official scrutiny, Dutch claims of effective regulation ring hollow.

 

Henk Jochemsen, PhD, is Director of the Lindeboom Institute for Medical Ethics.  John Keown, DPhil, is University Lecturer in the Law and Ethics of Medicine in the Faculty of Law, University of Cambridge.

 

References and notes

1 Washington v Glucksberg (1997) 117 S Ct 2258; Vacco v Quill (1997) 117 S Ct 2293.

2 Maas Pj van der et al. Medische beslissingen rond het levenseinde.

's-Gravenhage: SDU Uitgeverij Plantijnstraat, 1991 (published in translation as Euthanasia and other medical decisions concerning the end oflife.  Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1992).

3 See for example Jochemsen H. Euthanasia in Holland: an ethi­cal critique of the new law. _yournal of Medical Ethics 1994;20:212; Keown J. Euthanasia in the Netherlands: sliding down the slippery slope?  In: Keown J, cd.  Euthanasia examines.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995: ch 16.

4 Wal G van der, Maas Pj van der.  Euthanasie en andere niedische beslissingen rond het levenseinde.  De praktijk en de meldingsproce­dure. (Euthanasia and other medical decisions concerning the end of life. Practice and reporting procedure.) Den Haag: SDU uitgevers, 1996.  For summaries of the research in English see Maas Pj van der.  Euthanasia, physician-assisted suicide, and other medical practices involving the end of life in the Netherlands, 1990-1995.  New England _7ournal of Medicine 1996;335:1699; van der Wal G. Evaluation of the notification procedure for physician-assisted death in the Netherlands.  New England Jour­nal of Medicine 1996;335:1706.

5 See reference 4: 25.

6 See reference 4: tables 5.3; 6.2; 9. 1.

7 See reference 4: table 5.5.

8 Nederlands Juristenblad 1994; 69 nr26: 895ff.  See also Jochemsen H. The Netherlands experiment.  In: Kilner JF et al, eds.  Dignity and dying . Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1996: ch 12; Hendin H. Seduced by death: doctors, patients and the Dutch cure.  New York: WW Norton, 1997: ch 2.

9 Sorgdrager W, Borst-Eilers E. Euthanasie - De stand van zaken.  Medisch Contact 1995;12: 381-4.

10 Kastelijn WR.  Standpunt hoofdbestuur KWMG inzake euthana­sie.  Utrecht: KNMG, August 1995

11 See reference 4: table 5.4.

12 See reference 4: table 5.6.

13 See reference 4: table 5.12.

14 See reference 4: table 6.2; 92.

15 See reference 4: table 6.5.

16 This suggests a disturbing incidence not only of non-voluntary euthanasia but also of involuntary euthanasia.

17 See reference 4: table 6.4.

18 See reference 4: table 6.3.

19 See reference 4: table 6.6.

20 See reference 4: table 7.2.

This figure is calculated from the researchers'percentages and estimates at pages 92-93.  In fact the figure of 2,000 is conservative as Ħt is derived from the total number of 20,000 cases yielded by the physician-interviews rather than from the larger total of 25,800 in the death certificase study."Explicit" is the rescarchers' translation of the word "uitdrukkelijk".  We think a more accurate translation would be "primary" as a pur­pose can be explicit yet secondary or primary yet implicit.

21 See reference 4: 93.

22 See reference 4: table 7.4.

23 See reference 4: tables 7.3; 7.5.

24 See reference 4: tables 8. l; 8.3; 84.

25 See reference 4: tables 8.l; 8.3.

26 See reference 4: table 8.2.

27 See reference 4: 1 89.

28 See reference 4: table 17.2.

29 The researchers' estimate of 15 cases may be traced to their observation that in 17% of cases in which drugs were adminis­tered with the explicit intent to shorten life (totalling 15 cases), one of the drugs administered paralysed muscles and therefore caused death almost immediately whereas in a majority of cases in which drugs were administered in combination with the withdrawal oftreatment, the treatment withdrawn was artificial ventilation and the medication may have been administered to preyent suffocation.

30 See reference 4: table 17.3.

31 See reference 4: table 17.5.

32 See reference 4: table 1 S. l.

33 See reference S: Hendin: ch 2.

34 See reference 4: table 1 0. l.

35 See reference 4: table 10.2.

36 See text en page 19 immediately preceding reference 39.

37 The reason for the discrepancy between the two totals might be a certain bias in the physicians' responsos.  'ne authors of the survey suggest that some of the physicians interviewed, when asked to discuss their most recent case of euthanasia, in fact dis­cussed a recent case which had a stronger impact, probably because Ħt was reported.  See reference 4: 113.

38 See reference 4: 102-7.

39 See reference 4: table 1 l. 6.

40 See reference 4: table 1 I.S; 225.

41 14,200 of these cases involved no explicit request from the patient.  In cases where the patient had refused treatment, the doctors could properly, had they wished, have omitted treatment for this reason and without intent to shorten life.

Similarly, as was mentioned above, it is unclear in how many cases ofnon-treatment the treatment was in fact disproportion­ate and could properly have been withdrawn for that reason without the doctors resorting to an intention to shorten life.

42 See reference 4: 240.

43 See reference 4: 144-5.

44 See for example Angell M. Euthanasla in the Netherlands ­good news or bad?  New England Journal of Medicine 1996;335: 1677.

45 See for example Gomez C. Regulating death.  New York: Free Press, 1991; see reference 8: Hendin; see reference 3: Jochemsen; see reference 3: Keown.

46 While acknowledging this fact, Dr Angell suggests that doctors fail to report because they find the reporting procedure "burdensome" and "daunting".  See reference 44: 1677.  But it is difficult to see how the procedure - the filing of a report with the local medical examiner (another doctor) in the sure knowl­edge that if the guidelines have been followed there is no prospect of prosecution - can realistically be so describes.  Indeed, many doctors admit that they omit to report simply because they do not want the inconvenience of an investigation either for themselves or the family (see text at page 19 immediately preceding reference 40).

 

    Table 1 End-of-life decisions by doctors in the Netherlands 1990-1995

1990 1995
Deaths in the Netheriands 129000 (100%) 135500 (100%)
Requests for euthanasia 8900 (7%) 9700 (7.1%)
Euthanasia 2300 (I.S%) 3200 (2.4%)
Assisted suicide 400 (0.3%) 400 (0.3%)
Life-terminating acts without explicit request 1000 (0.8%) 900 (0.7%)
Intensification of pain and symptom treatment 22500 (17.5%) 20000 (14.8%)
    a. Explicitly intended to shorten life 1350 (I%)   2000 (I.S%)
    b. Partly intended to shorten life 6750 (5.2%) 2850 (2.1%)
    c. Taking into account the probability that life will be shortened 14400 (11.3%) 15150 (11.1%)
Withdrawal/withholding treatment (incl tube-feeding) 22500 (17.5%) 27300 (20.1%)
    a. At the explicit request of the patient 5800   (4.5%) 5200 (3.8%)
    b. Without the explicit request of the patient
        b1. Explicitly intended to shorten life 2670 (2.1%) 14200 (10.5%)
        b2. Partly intended to shorten life 3170 (2.5%)    -  
        b3. Taking into account the probability that life will be shortened 10850 (8.4%) 7900 (5.8%)
Intentional termination of neonates
    a. Without withholding/withdrawing treatment  -  10.00
    b. Withholding/withdrawing treatment plus administration of medication explicitly to shorten life   - 80.00
Assisted suicide of psychiatric patients 2-5